Comments by "MC116" (@angelmendez-rivera351) on "Spanning Tree" channel.

  1.  @theodoregossett9230  It does have to do with surjective functions, though, since the "size" of a set (technically, its cardinality or numerousity) is defined in terms of bijective functions. Two sets X, Y are equinumerous if and only if a bijection f : X —> Y exists. This is how equinumerousity is defined. Equinumerousity is an equivalence relation, and it partitions the universe of sets into equivalence classes, called cardinality classes. The cardinality class of a set X can be denoted |X|, and with the axiom of choice, these cardinality classes can be totally ordered. Now, we can say that for two sets X, Y, |X| =< |Y| if and only if there exists an injective function g : X —> Y. If X and Y are finite sets, then in order for them actually be finite, it must be the case that there exist functions p0 : X —> N, p1 : Y —> N which are injective, where N is the set of natural numbers, since this is how the finitude of a set is defined. To be able to say that |X| < |Y| is to be able to say that that some injective function g : X —> Y exists, but that no surjective function h : X —> Y exists. Your "formulation" of the pigeonhole principle, that if |X| < |Y| < |N|, then there is no injective function g : X —> Y, is a tautology, since the consequence is precisely the definition of the condition, and thus, this is not actually a formulation of the pigeonhole principle. Technically, the pigeonhole principle actually is the following statement: if |X| < |N|, and |Y| < |N|, and there exists a surjection h : X —> Y which is not injective, then |X| < |Y|. In essence, this is just saying that surjectivity and injectivity are dual, in the sense of category theory, at least when it comes to finite sets. Another formulation is to say that if |X| < |Y|, and Y is a subset of the power set of X, then there exists some S in Y such that |S| > 1. This one is the more straightforward formulation from the English wording.
    5
  2. 5
  3. 3
  4. 2
  5. 2
  6. 2
  7. 2
  8. 1
  9. 1
  10. 1
  11. 1
  12. 1
  13. 1
  14. 1
  15. 1
  16.  @ianbelletti6241  You can only double up items in the smaller set if the rules of the sets allow you to. This rule cannot apply if the rules of the specific sets prohibit that proposition. Remember, set theory does have real world applications. Calling it a general theorem is fine, but the rule for it to work is that positions in the smaller set are allowed to hold multiple values or items at once. If the smaller set cannot do this, then the theorem cannot be used for that situation. You almost have a point, but the insinuation here is that the axioms of set theory may be such that they allow for singletons, or the empty set, but no other sets. However, I do not know of any nontrivial, non ad hoc set theory, in which this is actually true. Any set theory in which the pigeonhole principle is false would also have to be a set theory in which the Schröder-Bernstein theorem is false, and even Cantor's theorem. There are situations where the theorem is false. It's the nature of these general theorems. There are no situations where the theorem is false. That is simply not how theorems work. You may say that there are situations where the theorem is not applicable, but by definition, a theorem is a sentence which can be proven, and the deduction rules used in mathematics are sound, meaning that it is impossible to prove false sentences from true sentences. Therefore, if a sentence is provable, then it cannot be false. Since the pigeonhole principle is provable, it cannot be false. In many cases they work, but under certain circumstances they don't. It's like the formula P=IE for power. It works in many cases but won't give you the true power because it doesn't take into account how many phases of electricity you're using and the impedance of the circuit. This analogy is invalid. The formula P = I•E is not a theorem, it is a scientific observation, a scientific law, and scientific laws do not work like theorems at all. You are comparing mathematics to physics here. This is like comparing apples and pineapples. Besides, no competent scientist would ever actually claim under any circumstances that the law works for all physical circuits. If someone tells ypu that it does, then they are lying to you. It is as simple as that. The same thing is happening with this theorem. No, it is not. Theorems are not scientific, and they do not work like scientific laws. They do not describe physical systems. In general it works, but it doesn't apply to all sets where you're inserting a larger set into a smaller set. I have no idea how you came to this conclusion. This is incoherent. No one is claiming you can embed the elements of a set into a smaller set. That is literally not what the pigeonhole principle states.
    1
  17. 1
  18. 1
  19. 1
  20. 1
  21. 1
  22. 1
  23. 1
  24. 1
  25. 1
  26. 1
  27. 1