Comments by "MC116" (@angelmendez-rivera351) on "How to Count" video.

  1. 2
  2. 2
  3. 2
  4. 1
  5. 1
  6. Regarding Galileo's paradox, you said that a function which matches every possible integer which is an even number with itself is injective. Fair enough, more integers than even numbers. But what about the follow-up: you have a function where each integer is assigned to its double, and it is a bijective function. How is that possible? I do not understand your question, but hopefully, what I will say is still helpful. The set of integers Z has a proper subset that we call the set of even integers, which we denote as 2Z. There are two functions that were mentioned in the video from 2Z to Z. The former function, f, is the function such that f(n) = n for all even integers n. f is an injection, but not a surjection, so it is not a bijection. The latter function, g, is the function such that g(n) = 2·n = n + n. g is an injection AND a surjection, so it is a bijection. The question that is important here is, do there exist any bijections from 2Z to Z at all? If the answer is no, then 2Z is smaller than Z, since an injection between 2Z to Z does exist. If the answer is yes, then 2Z is the same size as Z. So, what is the answer? The answer is yes: there exists at least one bijection from 2Z to Z, and g is one of those bijections (there are infinitely many such bijections, actually, g is just the simplest one to talk about). Actually, this gives us a hint as to why we denote the set of even integers as 2Z to begin with. If there are more integers than even integers, how is the second case showing a bijection and not an injection as well. It is not the case that there are more integers than even integers. I believe you are misunderstanding what the video is saying. Intuitively, one may think there are more integers than even integers, based on the fact that f is not a bijection, but g is a bijection, so despite what your intuition would say, 2Z and Z have the same size.
    1
  7. 1
  8. 1
  9. 1
  10. 1
  11. 1
  12. 1
  13. 1
  14. 1
  15. 1
  16. Is there any sense in which one set is still 'bigger' (scaled) compared to the other? The problem here is that you are conflating "scaled" and "bigger," as if they mean the same thing. They absolutely do not mean the same thing. In fact, the set 2Z is indeed a scalar multiple of Z, in the Minkowski scalar multiplication sense. For more information on what this means, you can read the Wikipedia article on "Minkowski sum." However, it is still true that |2Z| = |Z|. The problem that you are neglecting is that if you multiply |Z| by 2, you still get |Z|. Is this a problem with the notion of being able to 'count infinity'? No. What this is, it is a defining characteristic of infinite sets. Your intuition tells you that if A is a proper subset of B, then A is smaller than B. This is only true if A and B are finite sets. If you informally treat the cardinality of a set as a function output, with the set being the input, then you can view this as saying that the cardinality function is monotonic with respect to subsethood, but not strictly monotonic, even though your intuition is telling you that it must be strictly monotonic. Of course, this is just an analogy: cardinality is not a proper function. I suspect that something along this path is the break that allows the axiom of choice to lead to multiple copies of an object. No, not at all. Even if the axiom of choice is false, all countable sets are still the same size, even one is a proper subset of another. The axiom of choice has no bearing on that. What the axiom of choice does is it guarantees that the cardinalities of sets can be well-ordered, meaning that for every size of a set, there is always a well-defined "next size" or "next cardinality," and that if you have a set of sizes, that there is always a smallest size in that set of sizes.
    1
  17. 1
  18. 1
  19. 1
  20. 1
  21. 1
  22. 1
  23. 1
  24. 1
  25. 1
  26. 1
  27. 1
  28. 1
  29. 1
  30. 1
  31. 1
  32. 1
  33. 1
  34. 1
  35. 1
  36. 1
  37. 1
  38. 1
  39. 1