Comments by "eggynack" (@eggynack) on "TED-Ed" channel.

  1. 1
  2. 1
  3. 1
  4. 1
  5. 1
  6. 1
  7. 1
  8. 1
  9. 1
  10. 1
  11. 1
  12. 1
  13. 1
  14. 1
  15. 1
  16. 1
  17. 1
  18. 1
  19. 1
  20. 1
  21. 1
  22. 1
  23. 1
  24. 1
  25. 1
  26. 1
  27. 1
  28. 1
  29. 1
  30. 1
  31. I never really needed to "subtract" 24 from infinity, as it were. The set {25, 26, 27...} is already its own infinite set without ever needing to rely on a second infinite set. Phrasing it in terms of the natural numbers is convenient, but not necessary. Thus, any argument that relies on the presence of this process isn't all that effective. As for measuring infinity, yes you can. It just doesn't look the same as finite measures. For example, we can directly compare the size of the naturals and reals. The classic method is cardinality. Simply put, you attempt to map each element of set A to an element of set B and account for all of set B. If this is possible, then A is at least as big as B. Otherwise, B is strictly larger. Then you do the inverse, mapping B to A. If the first mapping and the second were possible, then the sets are the same size. Otherwise, well, I've already indicated how you identify one set as larger. Correspondingly, it is impossible to create such a mapping from the integers to the reals, but very possible to do so from the reals to the integers. So the set of reals is larger. Not every single thing we associate with measure will necessarily work properly. Percentage, for example, runs into issues. One of those issues is with cardinality itself though. If you take an infinite set, and then consider some finite non-zero percentage of that set, then that new set will always have the same cardinality as the original. Any attempt is necessarily somewhat problematic. You can certainly create something that seems like this 75%-ing though. Line the infinite piece of wood up with a number line, and mark any section that falls between a multiple of 4 and that value plus one. Then, take as your 75% everything left unmarked. What you'll be left with would, again, be as big as your original piece of wood, but it'd also be 75% However, this other type of measure, where we simply compare the size of two infinite sets, works fine. The Lebesgue measure works as well. This is where you create a set of open intervals that covers every element of the infinite set in question that covers the least space. The size of this least quantity of space is the Lebesgue measure. For any subset of the natural numbers, or even any subset of the rationals, the Lebesgue measure will always be zero. However, something like the interval (0,1), which is all the real numbers between those points, will have a Lebesgue measure of 1.
    1
  32. 1
  33. 1
  34. 1
  35. 1
  36. 1
  37. 1
  38. 1
  39. 1
  40. 1
  41. 1
  42. 1
  43. 1
  44. 1
  45. 1
  46. 1
  47. 1
  48. 1
  49. 1
  50. 1